It turned out to be sooner rather than later: A contribution to the ongoing discussion about §122 of Philosophical Investigations.
To begin with, a copy of a copy: Cavell, Existentialism and Analytical Philosophy, duplicating a paragraph from "Aesthetics and Modern Philosophy" (I cite the former because I don't have a copy of the latter handy):
In the Tractatus Wittgenstein says, "The solution of the problem of life is seen in the vanishing of the problem," and in the Investigations he says: "... the clarity we are aiming at is indeeed complete clarity. But this simply means that the philosophical problems should completely disappear." Yet he calls these problems solved (Investigations), and he says that when "there are... no questions left... this itself is the answer" (Tractatus). Putting these remarks together, the implication is that the problems of life and the problems of philosophy have the same form -- Wittgenstein would say they have the same "grammar": they are solved only when they disappear; answers are arrived at only when there are no longer questions. In the Investigations, this turns out to be more of an answer than, in this simple form, it seems to be; for here such an answer more explicitly dictates and displays the ways philosophy is to proceed in investigating problems, ways leading to what he calls "perspicuous representation," which means, roughly, that instead of accumulating new facts, or capturing the essence of the world in definitions, or perfecting and completing our language, we need to arrange the facts we already know or can come to realize merely by calling to mind something we know. Philosophical conflict, say as expressed in skepticism, does not arise from one party knowing facts the other party does not know. Wittgenstein also says that perspicuous representations are "the way we look at things," and he then asks "Is this a 'Weltanschauung'?" The answer to that question is, I take it, not No. Not, perhaps, Yes, because it is not a special, or competing, way of looking at things. But not No, because its mark of success is that the world seem --- be -- different.I think Cavell notices something which I took to be clear, but which Baker & Hacker both appears to disagree with Cavell & me on: what a "perspicuous presentation" (ubersichtlichen Darstellung) is. Wittgenstein says that this concept is of "fundamental importance" to us, that it "earmarks" (bezeichnet, names, labels) the form of account we give, the way we look at things. It "produces just that sort of understanding which consists in 'seeing connexions'"; this is said to be the reason "finding and inventing intermediate cases" is important.
The way I take all of this is -- the goal of Wittgenstein's approach to a philosophical problem is to attain a "perspicuous presentation" of the issues which have given rise to the problem -- to get a view of things which does not leave us wanting to ask questions which don't have answers (such as "how do I know that what I call "pain" is like what you call "pain"?"). Being "perspicuous" is just this quality of not being confusing to us (here, now, on this occasion) -- not leading us to ask the bad sort of questions, or make bad, "metaphysical" inferences from our everyday knowledge. And what is "presented" is nothing that was "hidden" in our everyday talk, nor something that we require a systematic treatment of our language-use to notice -- though a systematic treatment might be useful, in some cases! --; what is presented is just our everyday practices, which we were already familiar with. "Philosophy leaves everything as it is."
"A main source of our failure to understand is that we do not command a clear view of the use of our words. Our grammar is lacking in this sort of perspecuity." We fail to understand, to have the right sort of understanding, because we might not immediately notice that certain questions or assertions are nonsense; we can be wrong when we feel that we have a clear view of the words involved. We might need leading to see a piece of "disguised nonsense" for the patent nonsense it is.
Why is finding/inventing "intermediate cases" important? Not, I would argue, because this is somehow a "fundamentally important" "form of account" that Wittgenstein is concerned with presenting. The presentation of "intermediate cases" is important because the sort of understanding Wittgenstein aims at (and aims at cultivating) is one which consists in "seeing connexions" -- in seeing how things hang together. And presenting a confused consciousness with "intermediate cases", with cases where the connexions are more readily drawn, is a means to cultivate this sort of understanding. When one has this sort of view (which need not be a "bird's eye" or "God's eye" view), one doesn't ask questions about "how things hang together" which have no answer (such as "How does thought hook onto the world?"). Nor does one fall in for metaphysical rubbish which purports to explain how things hang together. (Seeing connexions means not imagining what connexions would have to be like.)
Based on n.n.'s post, Baker and Hacker both seem to take "perspicuous representations" as naming means to Wittgenstein's end, rather than Wittgenstein's end itself. (Though Baker seems to come close to my reading when he claims that "a 'perspicuous representation' is not a representation that is perspicuous, but a representation that renders perspicuous what it represents" -- though he seems to then go on to say that "all of the reminders of 'landmarks', the suggestions of 'patterns, analogies, pictures, etc. which enable us to find our way about in the motley of "our language"' will qualify as 'perspicuous representations." Whereas I don't want to call these anything more than -- helpful. They aren't of "fundamental importance" to Wittgenstein's "method", because there is no method in philosophy, and so nothing could be fundamentally important for that method. And neither can there be anything "fundamentally important" to the end Wittgensteinian philosophizing aims at, other than the end itself.)
And now, since n.n. was skeptical that his geography quotations allowed for a non-Hackensteinian reading, I shall attempt to give a non-Hackensteinian reading of the lot:
My aim is to teach you the geography of a labyrinth, so that you know your way about it perfectly. (MS 162b, 6v).
Knowing one's way about a labyrinth "perfectly" would just mean that one didn't go towards a dead-end at any point, or towards a wrong exit. There's no reason to assume that this imagery (which is basically that of the fly and the fly-bottle) is intended to hint at something like "conceptual topography." The geography/knowing-your-way-about talk could just be swapped out with talk of confusion & its avoidance.
The philosopher wants to master the geography of concepts. (MS 137, 63a)
I read this line two ways; I'm not sure quite what the context is, so I'm unable to get a firmer grip on it than that:"The philosopher" wants to do a lot of impossible things; "mastering the geography of concepts" might be no better a goal than "trying the grasp the incomparable essence of language" (PI 97). Alternately, this line may just be saying the same as the previous one: The philosopher wants to not get lost when he wanders in thought. He doesn't want to fall into paralogisms, antinomies, etc.
I am trying to conduct you on tours in a certain country. I will try to show you that the philosophical difficulties which arise in mathematics as elsewhere arise because we find ourselves in a strange town and do not know our way. So we must learn the topography by going from one place in the town to another, and from there to another, and so on. And one must do this so often that one knows one's way, either immediately or pretty soon after looking around a bit, wherever one may be set down.
This is an extremely good simile. In order to be a good guide, one should show people the main streets first.... The difficulty in philosophy is to find one's way about. (LFM, 44)
Suppose one had no guide when one was dropped into a strange city. One would wander around, not knowing where one was headed. And then after one had wandered around for long enough, one would instead be wandering around while knowing where one was headed (if one had been paying the least attention to one's surroundings). One might do this without ever drawing a map -- one simply "gets a feel" for the place.
If one has a guide, then the most helpful thing the guide can do is point out places where it is easy to get turned around, where the topography is unintuitive, and places which are hubs, which lead to many places (the "main streets"). This too might be done without ever drawing a map (even mental one).
In this "extremely good" simile, the main streets are the uses of the confusing bits of language which are not confusing to the one being guided; the guide aims to lead the wanderer to stop heading down blind alleys by pointing out the main streets, and leading the wanderer to learn how the alleys and streets line up -- the philosophical therapist aims to lead the confused thinker to stop trying to "dig below bedrock" by pointing out how things stand on the ground, and how the bedrock lies relative to the surface; how we use certain terms, and how their apparently metaphysical use stands to their everyday use.
One difficulty with philosophy is that we lack a synoptic view. We encounter the kind of difficulty we should have with the geography of a country for which we had no map, or else a map of isolated bits. The country we are talking about is language and the geography its grammar. We can walk about the country quite well, but when forced to make a map, we go wrong. (AWL, 43)
When forced to make a map!
I admit, I'm not sure what to make of this passage. But I will note that it's different than the earlier ones -- here the problem is not one of being lost or not (for "we can walk about the country quite well"), but of the difficulty of making a map. So it appears that these various geography-images don't share a common backing; they're just all places where Wittgenstein uses similar sorts of metaphors to convey some point or other.
I am inclined to connect this passage with the introduction to the Investigations: the "difficulty in philosophy" here is just that which prevented Wittgenstein from writing a "normal" book, with chapter-headings etc. But as he notes in that introduction, this isn't an accidental difficulty; the only way to go about this process is to "travel criss-cross in every direction." (And the only way to draw a map is through wandering around as one notes landmarks.)
Teaching philosophy involves the same immense difficulty as instruction in geography would have if a pupil brought with him a mass of false and falsely simplified ideas about the courses and connections of rivers and mountains. (BT, §90)
This geography-quote could be replaced with "...as instruction in poker... about the values of hands and how to spot a bluff." Any resemblance to "conceptual geography" is entirely superficial.
In order to know your way about an environment, you do not merely need to be acquainted with the right path from one district to another; you need also to know where you'd get to if you took this wrong turning. This shews how similar our considerations are to travelling in a landscape with a view to constructing a map. And it is not impossible that such a map will sometime get constructed for the regions that we are moving in. (RPP, §303)
The only sense in which I would need to know where I'd get to if I took a wrong turn, if what's at issue is whether or not I know my way about, is that I need to know how (if I took a wrong turn) I might get back on the route I wanted to be on. (For if I had to know where all the wrong turns would lead before I could be said to know my way around an environment, then the only way I could know my way around an environment would be to know my way around any environment that environment could lead to, since I could take wrong turn upon wrong turn, which is absurd.) So the sort of map in question here, I want to say, is the sort of map you're given as directions to a party (as opposed to the sort sold at gas stations). (I suspected I might be missing something from lack of context here, but a glance at the surrounding sections in the RPP seem to show that there is no context for this remark -- it's just there, between some remarks about pain and "inner processes".)
After several unsuccessful attempts to weld my results together into such a whole, I realized that I should never succeed. The best that I could write would never be more than philosophical remarks; my thoughts were soon crippled if I tried to force them on in any single direction against their natural inclination.—And this was, of course, connected with the very nature of the investigation. For this compels us to travel over a wide field of thought criss-cross in every direction.—The philosophical remarks in this book are, as it were, a number of sketches of landscapes which were made in the course of these long and involved journeyings.
The same or almost the same points were always being approached afresh from different directions, and new sketches made. Very many of these were badly drawn or uncharacteristic, marked by all the defects of a weak draughtsman. And when they were rejected a number of tolerable ones were left, which now had to be arranged and sometimes cut down, so that if you looked at them you could get a picture of the landscape. (PI, Preface)
Here the metaphor is just that of writing a book as being like painting a landscape. Wittgenstein is apologizing for the painting not being very good, just as he'd hoped that someone might do a better job at writing the Tractatus, in that book's introduction. Landscape painting, not cartography, is what is being gestured at here.
This may be compared to the way a chartered accountant precisely investigates and clarifies the conduct of a business undertaking. The aim is a synoptic comparative account of all the applications, illustrations, conceptions of the calculus. The complete survey of everything that may produce unclarity. And this survey must extend over a wide domain, for the roots of our ideas reach a long way. (Z, §273)
Here I think context is helpful:
273: Hardy: "That 'the finite cannot understand the infinite' should surely be a theological and not a mathematical war-cry." True, the expression is inept. But what people are using it to try and say is: "We mustn't have any juggling! How comes this leap from the finite to the infinite?" Nor is the expression all that nonsensical--only the 'finite' that can't conceive the infinite is not 'man' or 'our understanding', but the calculus. And HOW this conceives the infinite is well worth an investigation. This may be compared to the way a chartered accountant precisely investigates and clarifies the conduct of a business undertaking. The aim is a synoptic comparative account of all the applications, illustrations, conceptions of the calculus. The complete survey of everything that may produce unclarity. And this survey must extend over a wide domain, for the roots of our ideas reach a long way.--"The finite cannot understand the infinite" means here: It cannot work in the way you, with characteristic superficiality, are presenting it.I will admit that Wittgenstein does seem to have something like Hackenstein's approach in mind, here. Hackenstein's approach strikes me as a pretty decent way to handle confusions that arise from the misuse of a calculus. So, I am inclined to just concede this one: a Hackensteinian approach will get it about right. It's a fine tool for working with calculi.
Thought can as it were fly, it doesn't have to walk. You do not understand your own transactions, that is to say you do not have a synoptic view of them, and you as it were project your lack of understanding into the idea of a medium in which the most astounding things are possible.
A philosophical question is similar to one about the constitution of a particular society.
—And it's as if a group of people came together without clearly written rules, but with a need for them; indeed also with an instinct that caused them to observe certain rules at their meetings; but this is made difficult by the fact that nothing has been clearly articulated about this, and no arrangement has been made which brings the rules out clearly. Thus they in fact view one of their own as president, but he doesn't sit at the head of the table and has no distinguishing marks, and that makes negotiations difficult. That is why we come along and create a clear order: we seat the president at a clearly identifiable spot, seat his secretary next to him at a little table of his own, and seat the other full members in two rows on both sides of the table, etc., etc. (BT, §89)
"They in fact view one of their own as president, but he... has no distinguishing marks"strikes me as incoherent. If the president is identifiable as the guy that he is, then anything that allowed that guy to be distinguished would be a "distinguishing mark." And if the president isn't identifiable as the guy that he is, then I don't see how they could view him as their president. This paragraph does not strike me as being Wittgenstein at his best: The people are supposed to have an instinct to follow rules which they are unable to follow? How is that supposed to work? If I do a piss-poor job at something, it would be awfully strange to say I'm doing it instinctively -- instincts are supposed to be capabilities. (I can duck a ball instinctively. I can't try (and generally fail) to duck a ball instinctively. If I usually get hit by a ball when it's thrown at me, but flinch while it's approaching me, then all I'm doing "instinctively" is flinching, not repeatedly trying (and failing) to duck.)
I will note, though, that we are supposed to just be rearranging the seating-order here: We seat the president here, the secretary there, with an aim to making it easier to conduct meetings. We aren't making an organizational chart, and then using the chart to arrange with. The arrangement itself is said to "bring out the rules clearly" -- the rules don't get a further, explicit, formulation.
I also feel compelled to note that some countries have done perfectly well without written constitutions, and some have even argued that written constitutions are detrimental to the cause of the rule of law (since a written constitution can be adhered to in letter only while violated in spirit, but this is not possible when a nation's constitution is just its most central customary laws -- or at least it is much harder to simultaneously present an account of the law of the land which will be recognized as such and bend that law to be something it isn't). There are all sorts of things I don't like about this paragraph.
(I should probably finish Insight and Illusion at some point. I laid it down somewhere in the middle period; I remember finding Hacker's account of the "mystical" in the Tractatus hand-wavey.)
10 comments:
Baker and Hacker both seem to take 'perspicuous representations' as naming means to Wittgenstein's end, rather than Wittgenstein's end itself.
Doesn't Cavell do this as well? In the passage you quote, he implies that 'a perspicuous representation' is some sort of arrangement of "the facts we already know or can come to realize merely by calling to mind something we know." The effect of such an arrangement is that the philosophical problem disappears. Thus, it is a means to that end.
Cavell writes, "Wittgenstein also says that perspicuous representations are 'the way we look at things,' and he then asks 'Is this a "Weltanschauung"?' The answer to that question is, I take it, not No. Not, perhaps, Yes, because it is not a special, or competing, way of looking at things. But not No, because its mark of success is that the world seem — be — different." It's noteworty that Wittgenstein does not phrase this as a (rhetorical) question in the Big Typescript: "The concept of a surveyable representation is of fundamental significance for us. It designates our form of representation, the way we look at things (A kind of 'Weltanschauung', as is apparently typical of our time. Spengler.)" (§89)
What is 'presented' is nothing that was 'hidden' in our everyday talk, nor something that we require a systematic treatment of our language-use to notice — though a systematic treatment might be useful, in some cases! — ; what is presented is just our everyday practices, which we were already familiar with.
It is not hidden in the way in which a logical product of 'simpler' propositions is hidden in an 'unanalyzed' proposition (though cf. PI §664), but Wittgenstein does talk about things being 'hidden' because they're too familiar, i.e., we don't notice them because they're always in plain view. And by not noticing them, we forget about them. Thus, "The work of the philosopher consists in assembling reminders for a particular purpose" (BT §89), and "Learning philosophy is really recollecting. We remember that we really did use words that way." (BT §89) What is it that we have forgotten? We've forgotten that the same word can have different meanings. And this is the point of looking at different cases (seeing different aspects): "The particular peace of mind that occurs when we can place other similar cases next to one we thought was unique, occurs again and again in our investigations when we show that a word doesn't have just one meaning (or just two), but is used with five or six different meanings." (BT §89; this sentence occurs between the two sentences that occur as §§99-100 in TS 220). That is, we've forgotten that we really do use the same words in different ways. And we remember by considering helpful analogies, etc. These allow us to disentangle the different uses. We can then make these different uses perspicuous by tabulating them. Such a tabulation is a 'perspicuous representation'.
They aren't of 'fundamental importance' to Wittgenstein's 'method', because there is no method in philosophy, and so nothing could be fundamentally important for that method. And neither can there be anything 'fundamentally important' to the end Wittgensteinian philosophizing aims at, other than the end itself.)
What are we to make, then, of all of Wittgenstein’s references to the correct method in philosophy? For example, the title of §89 of the Big Typescript is "The Method of Philosophy: the Clearly Surveyable Representation of Grammatical Facts."
I'll see if I can find out the context for "The philosopher wants to master the geography of concepts."
One might do this without ever drawing a map — one simply 'gets a feel' for the place.
In fact, getting a feel for the place would not guarantee that one could draw a map: "It is very easy to imagine someone knowing his way about a city quite accurately, i.e., he finds the shortest way from one parts of the city to another quite surely — and yet that he should be perfectly incapable of drawing a map of the city. That, as soon as he tries, he only produces something completely wrong. (Our concept of 'instinct'.)" (RPP, §556; cf. BT §89 on 'instinct') Maps, it seems, are not solely useful for find one's way. In addition, they show the relationships between various paths and regions. Here, then, is a reason we would be 'forced' to make a map — we need to relate various regions of our grammar.
So the sort of map in question here, I want to say, is the sort of map you're given as directions to a party (as opposed to the sort sold at gas stations).
I don't know that this distinction serves your purpose. The sort of directions you describe amount to a tabulation of right and wrong turns. And a more or less comprehensive tabulation would be equivalent to a map 'sold at gas stations.'
Insight and Illusion is a good introduction, but I think you'd be better served with something more substantial, e.g., the 'Essays' volume of the revised Wittgenstein: Understanding and Meaning.
Thanks, I didn't feel like going through all those quotes one by one. Good point about the calculi example.
I'm not sure I really care that much about whether uDs are themselves a goal, or merely instrumental to the sort of understanding which, &c. (as long as we end up with the latter, that is). I also don't really care about whether we have a "method" in philosophy (which W. is "demonstrating, with examples" (§133)), or if the diversity of examples means we don't have a "method" after all. As long as whatever is supposed to happen happens.
One last thing is that I don't think we gain that much from playing "dueling proof-texts" using the Nachlass. Not only do we lose the context (as you've noted – even if we quote the neighboring sections in whatever "book" we're taking it from), but I always want to ask: if this idea is so important then why isn't it in (the analogous sections in) the PI? Maybe it was an idea that he was tempted by, but later (or earlier) saw as a temptation to be resisted (i.e. along with the other ones).
I'll try to say a few things of my own later on. (Of course, I've made that promise before, haven't I.)
I always want to ask: if this idea is so important then why isn't it in (the analogous sections in) the PI? Maybe it was an idea that he was tempted by, but later (or earlier) saw as a temptation to be resisted (i.e. along with the other ones).
I think this assumes that the Investigations is the polished picture of his later philosophy and the rest of the Nachlass is either leading up to it or a post script to it. I think that is a misleading way to view the PI and the rest of the Nachlass. Remember that the PI was not published by Wittgenstein. And while he was preparing it (or some book) for publication, wrote an introduction, etc., he did these things a number of times for a number of different typescripts. After he finished what we have as the PI, he reworked much of its content in later manuscripts and typescripts. Just think of how many texts have been published which post-date the PI). Are these later texts more authoritative than the Investigations?
I know all that, and of course the assumption in your first sentence is too strong (so no, I'm not making it). But you can't deny that the PI (or at least §§1-300) has a tight, carefully planned-out structure missing in virtually everything else, including later texts. There's some good stuff in the Nachlass though, no question. I just think (as with Nietzsche) that we should be *really* careful with poring over it for proof-texts.
Sorry, I didn't mean to suggest that you didn't know all that.
I agree that the PI is a carefully planned text, and that caution is needed in quoting other texts in the Nachlass. However, if an earlier text, especially one as important as the Big Typescript, has something to say on a topic in the Investigations, I am inclined to accept the earlier statements unless there is good reason to believe that Wittgenstein later rejected them. Otherwise, it's difficult to avoid being arbitrary.
Ah you pleased your monarchist bosses, s-Dan. If "meaning as use" really holds (or Mad Ludwig's pop-gestalt idea of Sprach-spiel), then rappers = Ezra Pound.
The mistakes of the TLP (like a denial of induction and probability, in toto) are a bit more interesting.
(uh, and here's something to consider: are the codes of the New Testament (which you claim to uphold) and the proverbs of St. Witt. compatible, er, sympatico??? No creo que. Even Lord Bertie's a bit closer to, like, purgatorio)
On Cavell: I read the passage quoted as identifying "perspicuous representation" with the "weltanschauung?" at the end of the paragraph. The ways in which philosophy proceeds lead to "perspicuous representation"; the bit about "rearranging" and "calling to mind" is describing the way in which the Investigations "dictates and displays" the way philosophy proceeds towards the end of seeing things -- things being -- different. Though I think Duck is right that nothing big hinges on the means/end distinction, here; it just struck me funny that the Baker-Hacker debate over §122 seemed to be totally orthogonal to the way I am inclined to read the passage.
The fact that the Big Typescript doesn't have a question-mark at the end of the "Weltanschauung" make me think of the PI's preface-reference to discarding some earlier formulations as "the defects of a weak draughtsman". The question-mark strikes me as changing the remark quite a bit, and I much prefer the version with the question-mark. (Though I've not read Spengler -- is there anything remarkable about his use of "worldview"-talk, or is LW just noting where he picked up the term? From what I've heard of "The Decline of the West" I'd guess the latter, but it seems worth asking, just in case.) -- That there exist two versions of that passage is odd, though. This probably speaks to how much of a work-in-progress the latter work was; I'm reminded of LW's marginal note to §133 of "That's a lie!"
You are of course right that the distinction between the Investigations and all of the other post-exilic writing is somewhat arbitrary, since LW didn't publish any of them. But where something from the Nachlass clashes with my understanding of the Investigations, I'm generally inclined to let the PI retain its integrity. After all, there's no reason Wittgenstein can't occasionally contradict himself, when he's writing & thinking over the course of some decades, and there's no reason to assume every new thought is going to be an improvement over an old one (or vice-versa). And the PI just strikes me as having a higher signal-to-noise ratio than what I've read of the other later works. (The fact that Wittgenstein was so often critical of his own writing, and his own skills as a thinker, incline me to think I'm not being utterly reckless as a hermeneut, here. If Wittgenstein wanted all his papers destroyed after his death, then there had better be some utter crap in there!)
You make a fair point in re: things being hidden because they're too familiar ("like a pair of glasses on our nose"). My rhetoric got away from me there (in general this post reads a little more aggressively than I'd prefer). And I agree that Wittgenstein is often concerned with gathering together various uses of certain words, helpful analogies, etc. with an aim of making the use of particular terms clear. But I think that "tabulating" the various uses is often not needed -- just being reminded that certain words are used in multiple ways can itself be enough to make what seemed deep, or paradoxical, or Significant, cease to appear so. (And if it doesn't, I'm not sure that drawing up a list of all the everyday uses of a term (in a "perspicuous representation") is going to help -- the befuddled can always maintain that the list ignores the sense in which they are using the word now, and if you think they're speaking nonsense, or violating "logical grammar" or somesuch, this just shows that you don't appreciate the deep seriousness of the problems they are contemplating -- the sense in which they are using a term ~philosophically~, and so of course not in any "ordinary" sense. Such cases need a different sort of therapy applied.)
On Wittgenstein's references to "method" (singular): Let's look at PI§133:
"The real discovery is the one that makes me capable of stopping doing philosophy when I want to.—The one that gives philosophy peace, so that it is no longer tormented by questions which bring itself in question.—Instead, we now demonstrate a method, by examples; and the series of examples can be broken off.—Problems are solved (difficulties eliminated), not a single problem.
There is not a philosophical method, though there are indeed methods, like different therapies."
"There is not a philosophical method, though there are indeed methods" -- this seems unambiguous enough. And Wittgenstein can very well be interested in demonstrating methods which are useful in philosophy (as he is in the immediately preceding paragraph) without contradicting this. As for references to "the method in philosophy", I think the only thing to say is -- Wittgenstein slipped up. When he speaks of "the method in philosophy", he goes against his best insights. (It strikes me as unlikely that he'd slip up in the other direction -- claim that there is not a single method, but only multiple methods, when he really knew there was a single "genuine" one. But slipping up in the opposite direction strikes me as easy to do -- you simply move to praise a particular method, and all of a sudden you've said something that's too strong.)
I am more inclined to stress that "There is not a method in philosophy" than Duck is, but this may partly be due to my Systematic Theology professor's strong urge to discuss "method" when I didn't think there was any sense to doing so; arguing with him was the original reason I looked at Wittgenstein, since he appealed to Wittgenstein (and Macintyre) for the particular "method" he claimed to be employing. (I disagreed with him both that "method" was important in these areas, and that he had in fact been using the "method" he appealed to, and made us regurgitate on the Systematic I mid-term. Fun discussions. But I digress -- my point is that I've gotten decent mileage out of arguing against "methodism".)
I worry that the "map" metaphor may be having more weight put on it than it can safely bear, but I agree that one can "know one's way about" without being able to draw a map. (I am reminded of the centipede who knows how to walk until someone asks him how he coordinates so many legs, at which point he becomes frozen in place.) But I'm not sure how it's relevant to the "extremely good simile" passage -- what a guide needs to do to be a good guide is to know his way about, and be able to teach others to know their way about; he doesn't need to be able to draw distinctions about how the area is "laid out" beyond this. (Whereas a city planner would need the latter sort of information, and so probably does require a map to do his job. I am inclined to note that Washington D.C. is hellish to drive in, and not much better to navigate my foot, but it's very aesthetically pleasing if you look at it from the air -- the damnable circle-streets are pretty if you are a bird. And the city was very heavily planned-out, consciously designed, to be like it is. The map-making/knowing-your-way-about opposition can go both ways, I think.) "Needing to relate various regions of our grammar" strikes me as being more the affair of a city planner than a guide -- if I want to know my way around my language, it may be superfluous. (Again, I suspect the "extremely good simile" may be showing its seams.)
If you think the sort of map one is given for finding a party is something like a "tabulation of right and wrong turns", then you must have better hosts than I've been privy to. More than once, the "map" I've been given is just a few rectangles (sometimes buildings, sometimes streets, sometimes both ambiguously) and a single line to indicate the proper path (on one occasion, there were not even street names written -- you had to rely on your knowledge of the area around the campus to figure out which end of the line was the start and which the finish). It strikes me as odd to think of this sort of slap-dash cartography as being like a normal roadmap, only less comprehensive, or as being like a list of right & wrong turns. In some cases it wouldn't be identifiable as a map at all, if it weren't printed below a street address & contact information. But it does a passable job at informing one how to find the place in question, generally.
(Another one just occurred to me -- the map was a series of rectangles & a single line, as normal, with the destination street's name printed. What was easy to overlook was that the name was printed backwards. As was the entire map. Somehow it'd gotten flipped on the copy-machine, so a mirror image of the intended map was what was handed out. And this wasn't noticed until several people had already headed out. Not exactly a perspicuous representation. But for the people that noticed the misprint, it was a usable map.)
ToSsy: Now you've made me want to hear Ezra Pound performed in rap.
Forgot to ask: What is the parallel for PI§133 look like in the Big Typescript? It'd be interesting if Wittgenstein only adopted the "There is not a method in philosophy" line fairly late in the game.
Ah you dodged the question of Wittgenstein's abode in the Malebolge, S-dan, the "theology" student: alas, he's stuffed into shit, along with many other philosophasters.
You're better off with Ezra Pound's prose (and poesy), even in terms of your language follies. (and, somewhere, I wager Descartes agrees). Jus' sayin'.
Daniel,
Drop me a line at empty_reference@yahoo.com, and I'll send you the Diamond article.
Post a Comment